Thomas Hobbes is a British philosopher, born in 1588. Among his prolific work, one book will become one of the major founder pieces of the modern political thought; Leviathan (1651). In this work, Hobbes writes about the natural condition of mankind, and its consequences. He thus joins the lineage of the social contract's philosophers, such as Jean-Jacques Rousseau or John Locke. One may ask why we shall bother to study such old pieces of writing; the answer is actually quite simple. The theory of the social contract is the very base of our whole political society, and some aspects of Hobbes work are still helpful to understand our world; as an example, many actual or recent totalitarian states have found a justification to their exaction in Hobbes's work.
In Leviathan, Hobbes is actually trying to justify the imposition of the political authority, the metaphorical Leviathan. In order to prove his point, that "a life without government is not worth living" (Newey, 2008, p2), Hobbes uses his own analysis of the natural condition of mankind, the state of nature, which could be defined as "the simple condition where we are forced into contact with each other in the absence of a superior authority that can lay down and enforce rules to govern our behavior toward each other" (Ryan, 2009, p217-218). What is then the natural condition of mankind, and why did this consideration lead to the necessity of the strong Leviathan state?
We will first study the main features of the Hobbesian man, in order to determine the consequences of the above mentioned nature on the interactions between men in the state of nature, and to finally see why the Leviathan became necessary.
[...] What for Hobbes was the ‘natural condition of mankind' and why did it necessitate the Leviathan state? Thomas Hobbes is a British philosopher, born in 1588. Among his prolific work, one book will become one of the major founder pieces of the modern political thought; Leviathan (1651). In this work, Hobbes writes about the natural condition of mankind, and its consequences. He thus joins the lineage of the social contract's philosophers, such as Jean-Jacques Rousseau or John Locke. One may ask why we shall bother to study such old pieces of writing; the answer is actually quite simple. [...]
[...] In this state of nature, every human is trying to survive by satisfying its own desires, regardless of the others' ones. Life would actually be easy if the earth was peopled with a single human being; as an example, if he was starving, he would only need to pick a fruit on a tree. However, there is not one only human being, but many of them, and according to Hobbes's postulate, more than the earth's supply could satisfy. Our friend will then see other human beings, starving as well, and then craving for the same fruit. [...]
[...] Nevertheless, Hobbes's conception of the birth of the State is still dominant in the current political thought, and must not be forgotten. Bibliography - Hampsher-Monk, I. (1992), A history of modern political thought, Cambridge: Basil Blackwell Inc. - Hobbes, T. (1996), Leviathan, Oxford: Oxford University Press. - Newey, G. (2008), Hobbes and Leviathan, Oxon: Routledge. - Ryan, A. (2009), Hobbes's political philosophy in Sorrel, T. [...]
[...] We have seen before that Hobbesian men were equals, and rational. Therefore, we can deduce of those two statements that men would see each of his fellow men as a threat. The rational Hobbesian individual man would then be likely to launch pre-emptive attacks against other men; thinking which dominates in the state of nature can be summed up in the old adage that attack is the best form of violence” (Newey p77). Everyone is treating everybody else as an enemy, which leads to the war of all against all, making the state of nature a state of perpetual war. [...]
[...] Cambridge companion to Hobbes, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [...]
Source aux normes APA
Pour votre bibliographieLecture en ligne
avec notre liseuse dédiée !Contenu vérifié
par notre comité de lecture